Table of Contents
- 1. Anarchism
- 1.1. Constructing an Anarchism: Collective Force anarchism philosophy
- 1.2. Existentialism is a Humanism philosophy
- 1.3. God is Evil, Man is Free anarchism philosophy religion
- 1.4. Liberatory Community Armed Self-Defense: Approaches Toward a Theory anarchism
- 1.5. TODO My Disillusionment in Russia anarchism history
- 1.6. No Treason. No. VI. The Constitution of No Authority (1870) anarchism
- 1.7. Polity-form and External constitution anarchism philosophy
- 1.8. Simple Sabotage Field Manual anarchism direct_action
- 1.9. The Anarchic Encounter: Economic and/or Erotic? anarchism philosophy jobs
- 1.10. The Anatomy of the Encounter anarchism philosophy
- 1.11. The Collected Writings of Renzo Novatore philosophy anarchism
- 1.12. The Difference between Anarchy and the Academy anarchism
- 1.13. The Myth of the Rule of Law anarchism philosophy
- 1.14. The Politics of Obedience: The Discourse of Voluntary Servitude anarchism philosophy
- 1.15. Ur-Fascism philosophy
- 1.16. Are We Good Enough? - Peter Kropotkin anarchism philosophy
- 1.17. Post-Left
- 1.17.1. A Review of The “Tyranny of Structurelessness”: An organizationalist repudiation of anarchism anarchism
- 1.17.2. Anarchism as a Spiritual Practice anarchism religion
- 1.17.3. Bloody Rule and a Cannibal Order! anarchism
- 1.17.4. TODO Communism Unmasked anarchism philosophy
- 1.17.5. Hayek, Epistemology, and Hegemonic Rationality philosophy anarchism
- 1.17.6. Natural Law, or Don’t Put a Rubber on Your Willy philosophy anarchism
- 1.17.7. The Question of a Stagnant Marxism: Is Marxism Exegetical or Scientific? philosophy
- 1.17.8. The Union of Egoists anarchism philosophy
- 1.17.9. The Unique and Its Property philosophy
- 1.17.10. Toward the queerest insurrection anarchism queer
- 1.17.11. Post-Left Anarchy anarchism philosophy post_left
- 1.17.12. Smashing the Orderly Party anarchism
- 1.17.13. Software and Anarchy anarchism programming software
- 1.17.14. Some Thoughts on the Creative Nothing philosophy
- 1.17.15. Stirner's Critics philosophy
- 1.17.16. Critique of "Left-Wing" Culture
- 1.17.16.1. Transmisogyny transmisogyny
- 1.17.16.2. I Am A Transwoman. I Am In The Closet. I Am Not Coming Out. transmisogyny
- 1.17.16.3. Hot Allostatic Load transmisogyny
- 1.17.16.4. How Twitter can ruin a life: Isabel Fall’s complicated story
- 1.17.16.5. Shaming Isn’t Shielding: The Moral Panics That Cry Wolf praxis
- 1.17.16.6. Fandom, purity culture, and the rise of the anti-fan
- 1.17.16.7. Post-Left vs “Woke” Left anarchism post_left
- 1.17.16.8. The “Stirner Wasn’t A Capitalist You Fucking Idiot” Cheat Sheet philosophy anarchism
- 1.17.16.9. Vampire Castle post_left
- 1.17.16.10. Anarchism and the politics of ressentiment anarchism post_left
- 1.17.16.11. Why Has Critique Run out of Steam? From Matters of Fact to Matters of Concern critical_theory
- 1.17.16.12. What’s the harm in reading? culture
- 1.18. Market Anarchism
- 1.18.1. Markets Not Capitalism anarchism
- 1.18.2. TODO Anarchists Against Democracy In Their Own Words anarchism philosophy
- 1.18.3. Anarchy without Hyphens (1980) anarchism philosophy
- 1.18.4. Anarchy in the U.K. anarchism history
- 1.18.5. Anatomy of the State anarchism philosophy
- 1.18.6. Confiscation and the Homestead Principle (1969) anarchism philosophy economics
- 1.18.7. Corporations versus the Market; or, Whip Conflation Now anarchism economics
- 1.18.8. Economic Calculation in the Corporate Commonwealth, Hierarchy or the Market, and Contract Feudalism philosophy anarchism
- 1.18.9. From Whence Do Property Titles Arise? anarchism philosophy
- 1.18.10. In Defense of Public Space anarchism philosophy economics
- 1.18.11. Instead of a Book, by a Man Too Busy to Write One: A Fragmentary Exposition of Philosophical Anarchism anarchism
- 1.18.12. Labour Struggle in a Free Market anarchism economics
- 1.18.13. Nice Shit for Everybody anarchism philosophy
- 1.18.14. TODO Property is Theft! A Pierre-Joseph Proudhon Anthology philosophy anarchism economics
- 1.18.15. Revealed Preference: A Parable anarchism economics
- 1.18.16. Scratching By: How Government Creates Poverty as We Know It anarchism economics
- 1.18.17. TODO Seeing Like A State: How Certain Schemes to Improve the Human Condition Have Failed anarchism economics philosophy
- 1.18.18. The Gift Economy of Property anarchism philosophy
- 1.18.19. THe Modern Business Corporation versus the Free Market? anachism economics
- 1.18.20. The Network: A Parody of the Discourse anarchism economics parody
- 1.18.21. The Question of Copyright philosophy anarchism
- 1.18.22. The Right to Self-Treatment anarchism economics
- 1.18.23. The Use of Knowledge in Society anarchism economics
- 1.18.24. Why Market Exchange Doesn’t Have to Lead to Capitalism anarchism economics
- 1.18.25. Health Care and Radical Monopoly anarchism market
1. Anarchism
1.1. Constructing an Anarchism: Collective Force anarchism philosophy
"The basic idea is that the things that we do together with others do not simply add up, but that specialization and association bring about the formation of unity-collectivities, social beings with qualities, strengths and perhaps even ideas that arise from the combination and unification of the constituent beings."
Perhaps the most useful conceptual tool from Proudhon by way of Shawn that I've seen, besides the anarchic encounter.
1.2. Existentialism is a Humanism philosophy
This is a really excellent lecture by Sartre, giving a basic account of what existentialism is. Although I'm an amoralist, and as such don't agree with everything it says, it is an eloquent expression of many ideas also to be found in the likes of Stirner, except stated in a more comprehensible (to most people) way. I'm even sympathetic to what he has to say about morality – it's worth thinking about, and may inform your own nihilist ethics.
1.3. God is Evil, Man is Free anarchism philosophy religion
Fiery, provocative, dense, sometimes somewhat difficult to read, but also an intelligent, clear-sighted, and funny, and nuanced critique of the common idea of the Christian God from Proudhon. I really enjoy reading this every so often.
:ID: 64e23274-63b1-44d6-839a-2706ca491f9f
1.4. Liberatory Community Armed Self-Defense: Approaches Toward a Theory anarchism
The best exposition in one place I've found of how to actually go about defending your community with arms that wouldn't just lead to a militia or something. Worth reading for all anarchists.
1.5. TODO My Disillusionment in Russia anarchism history
A classic anarchist text that I really need to read soon considering I'm surrounded by damned Marxists.
1.6. No Treason. No. VI. The Constitution of No Authority (1870) anarchism
A thorough – and humerous! – takedown of any possible authority one might consider the Constitution of the United States to have, assuming only that one believes that the majority does not have an automatic and inherent right to dominate the individual, and that one should only be bound by a contract one agrees to.
1.7. Polity-form and External constitution anarchism philosophy
Two more excellent conceptual tools that I make use of often, although often not with those exact terms, explored by Shawn. I initially picked up these ideas from other scattered bits in other essays of his, but this glossary entry really brings it together well, after having read through it, as long as you're willing to carefully read every line (it's densely packed with ideas).
1.8. Simple Sabotage Field Manual anarchism direct_action
Most manuals on how to take direct actions like sabotage suggest things that are actively dangerous, either to the person doing it, or the innocent people around, or both, and/or can have very serious lasting consequences if you're detected. Many are also of doubtful efficacy, no matter how satisfying they may be (such as Molotoving some Starbucks or Walmart somewhere, or setting a few cop cars on fire). All of these have their place in a complete, well rounded diversity of tactics – even the ones that are only of propagandistic or symbolic value – but for most people, who have lives to lose and are generally risk averse (this, unfortunately, includes me, despite my love for Novatore), those manuals aren't particularly useful, except as a sort of performance art in the reading.
This book, however, provides a simple, easy to practice, manual for sabotaging the processes of bureaucracies of various sorts, if you believe that they're up to no good – for instance, if you're part of an arm of a corporation or state that's doing something bad, or an average citizen being roped into e.g. tracking down a criminal – without jeopardizing yourself in any significant way. These methods, while simple and easy, are also relatively effective due to the way hierarchical systems and bureaucracies work.
The classic section:
(11) General Interference with Organizations and Production
(a) Organizations and Conferences (1) Insist on doing everything through “channels.” Never permit short-cuts to be taken in order to expedite decisions.
(2) Make “speeches.” Talk as frequently as possible and at great length. Illustrate your “points” by long anecdotes and accounts of personal experiences. Never hesitate to make a few appropriate “patriotic” comments.
(3) When possible, refer all matters to committees, for “further study and consideration.” Attempt to make the committees as large as possible—never less than five.
(4) Bring up irrelevant issues as frequently as possible.
(5) Haggle over precise wordings of communications, minutes, resolutions.
(6) Refer back to matters decided upon at the last meeting and attempt to re-open the question of the advisability of that decision.
(7) Advocate “caution.” Be “reasonable” and urge your fellow-conferees to be “reasonable” and avoid haste which might result in embarrassments or difficulties later on.
(8) Be worried about the propriety of any decision—raise the question of whether such action as is contemplated lies within the jurisdiction of the group or whether it might conflict with the policy of some higher echelon.
(b) Managers and Supervisors
(1) Demand written orders.
(2) “Misunderstand” orders. Ask endless questions or engage in long correspondence about such orders. Quibble over them when you can.
(3) Do everything possible to delay the delivery of orders. Even though parts of an order may be ready beforehand, don’t deliver it until it is completely ready.
(4) Don’t order new working materials until your current stocks have been virtually exhausted, so that the slightest delay in filling your order will mean a shutdown.
(5) Order high-quality materials which are hard to get. If you don’t get them argue about it. Warn that inferior materials will mean inferior work.
(6) In making work assignments, always sign out the unimportant jobs first. See that the important jobs are assigned to inefficient workers of poor machines.
(7) Insist on perfect work in relatively unimportant products; send back for refinishing those which have the least flaw. Approve other defective parts whose flaws are not visible to the naked eye.
(8) Make mistakes in routing so that parts and materials will be sent to the wrong place in the plant.
(9) When training new workers, give incomplete or misleading instructions.
(10) To lower morale and with it, production, be pleasant to inefficient workers; give them undeserved promotions. Discriminate against efficient workers; complain unjustly about their work.
(11) Hold conferences when there is more critical work to be done.
(12) Multiply paper work in plausible ways.
Start duplicate files.
(13) Multiply the procedures and clearances involved in issuing instructions, pay checks, and so on. See that three people have to approve everything where one would do.
(14) Apply all regulations to the last letter.
1.9. The Anarchic Encounter: Economic and/or Erotic? anarchism philosophy jobs
In this essay Shawn expands on the notion of the anarchic encounter to talk about its possibilities – what can be born out of it. It's interesting and inspiring.
1.10. The Anatomy of the Encounter anarchism philosophy
Shawn's explications of Proudhonian anarchist/libertarian socialist theory are always deeply interesting and enlightening, providing me with new concepts in my intellectual toolkit. His work on the anarchic encounter, a sort of Crusoe-economics look at the ideal anarchistic social relations that can be used to guide our practical interactions and organization, but also our conceptions of justice, is some of the most enlightening. In this essay, he introduces that concept.
1.11. The Collected Writings of Renzo Novatore philosophy anarchism
There is perhaps no writer that has influenced me more than the philosopher-poet and Nietzschean/Stirnerian hybrid anarchist Novatore. His writings have a wonderful vitality and strength and life and individuality to them, and a really fun need to strike back with poetic, beautiful, yet vicious anger at the fascists, unconscious egoists and communitarians that would drag us all down. I've read a lot of these, but not all, and I really should reread them. The ones I've read and really liked are:
- Black Flags
- Cry of Rebellion
- Intellectual Vagabonds
- Toward the Creative Nothing
- Anarchist Individualism in the Social Revolution
- My Iconoclastic Individualism
- I Am Also A Nihilist
A quote from Black Flags that seems relevant in our times:
Our time — despite empty and contrary appearances — is already lying on all fours under the heavy wheels of a new History.
The bestial morality of our bastard christian-liberal-bourgeois-plebeian civilization turns toward the sunset…
Our false social organization is collapsing fatally — inexorably!
The fascist phenomenon is the surest, most indisputable proof of it.
In Italy as elsewhere…
To show it, one would only have to go back in time and question history. But even this isn’t necessary! — The present speaks eloquently enough…
Fascism is nothing but a cruel, convulsive spasm of a decaying society that tragically drowns in the quagmire of its lies.
Because it — fascism — indeed celebrates its bacchanals with flaming pyres and malicious orgies of blood; but the dull crackling of its livid fires doesn’t give off a single spark of vivid innovative spirituality; meanwhile, may the blood that pours out be transformed into wine, that we — the forerunners of the time — silently gather in red goblets of hatred setting it aside as the heroic beverage to pass on to the children of the night and of sorrow in the fatal communion of great revolt.
We will take these brothers of ours by the hand to march together and climb together toward new spiritual dawns, toward new auroras of life, toward new conquests of thought, toward new feasts of light; new solar noons.
Because we are lovers of liberating struggle.
We are the children of sorrow that rises and thought that creates.
We are restless vagabonds.
The boldest in every endeavor; the tempter of every ordeal.
And life is an “ordeal”! A torment! A tragic flight. — A fleeting moment!
1.12. The Difference between Anarchy and the Academy anarchism
A very useful short essay outlining the ways in which the academy can be useful to anarchist causes, is praiseworthy, can offer things to imitate to us, and also the ways in which it is structurally contrary to anarchism, can hurt our causes, and is deeply flawed and problematic, and how someone who wants to be an anarchist academic, instead of an academic anarchist, might navigate those issues. This is an essay that hits close to home as someone who was forced to drop out of university a year before finishing my Bachelor's due to disability, and has serious problems with the academy and the culture and tendencies of those who stay there a long time, but also sees the ways in which it's really useful and good too.
1.13. The Myth of the Rule of Law anarchism philosophy
- Law is inherently indeterminate:
- It contains a large amount of diametrically contradicting decisions, cases, precedent, and rules, and anything can be logically derived from conflicting premises
- There is no such thing as language that does not admit of interpretation and reinterpretation, and thus even clearly written law texts can really be understood to mean anything
- As a result, a legal argument can be found for any conclusion, and any conclusion is pretty much as valid as any other, even if they're diametrically opposed. What the law "means," and thus how it is interpreted, argued, and enforced, is totally up to the moral and political beliefs of the individuals doing it.
- Moreover, law is always, universally produced by political actors, who will encode their values into it.
- The apperance of the stability in meaning of the law is merely a product of the stability in the values of those who interpret it, due to social selection processes and indoctrination, and the "meaning" of the law can be seen to change as who interprets it changes.
- Furthermore, law cannot be anything but indeterminate, because if it was completely rigid, absolute, and clear – assuming for a moment such a thing were even possible, which it isn't – then, while it would be able to mete our order, it wouldn't be able to mete out justice, because it wouldn't be able to take into account context, individual cases, and complex human values.
- Law cannot be anything but indeterminate, also, because it is a monopoly product, produced by the state and provided one-size-fits-all for everyone, so it has to be flexible enough to make that at least a little feasible. (This rather nicely and summarily puts to bed Rothbard's project in The Ethics of Liberty)
- Most Americans are clearly both aware that there is no such thing as the "rule of law, not people" in how they jockey for control of law, but at the same time seem to believe in it. This cognitive dissonance is because the myth of the rule of law is otherwise emotionally useful. Namely, because it naturalizes law, as being neutral, objective encodings of justice, and thus part of the natural social order, which:
- allows people deniability when they enforce their values, or the dominant social values they don't want to have to stand against, on others
- enables people to view their moral positions, as filtered through their construction of the meaning of the law, as neutral, objective, and necessary, and their oponents' interpretations as biased and politically-motivated
- Americans also subscribe to this idea because it has been indoctrinated into them by the state. It is convenient for the state for people to believe in the rule of law because then people are more willing to submit themselves to it, and make others submit to it.
- If we stop viewing law as something that must be supplied centrally, we can avoid the problem of one-size-fits-all law, and difficult to interpret law, and power structures around law.
1.14. The Politics of Obedience: The Discourse of Voluntary Servitude anarchism philosophy
Classic quote from this work:
When not a hundred, not a thousand men, but a hundred provinces, a thousand cities, a million men, refuse to assail a single man from whom the kindest treatment received is the infliction of serfdom and slavery, what shall we call that? Is it cowardice? Of course there is in every vice inevitably some limit beyond which one cannot go. Two, possibly ten, may fear one; but when a thousand, a million men, a thousand cities, fail to protect themselves against the domination of one man, this cannot be called cowardly, for cowardice does not sink to such a depth, any more than valor can be termed the effort of one individual to scale a fortress, to attack an army, or to conquer a kingdom. What monstrous vice, then, is this which does not even deserve to be called cowardice, a vice for which no term can be found vile enough, which nature herself disavows and our tongues refuse to name?
[…]
Poor, wretched, and stupid peoples, nations determined on your own misfortune and blind to your own good! You let yourselves be deprived before your own eyes of the best part of your revenues; your fields are plundered, your homes robbed, your family heirlooms taken away. You live in such a way that you cannot claim a single thing as your own; and it would seem that you consider yourselves lucky to be loaned your property, your families, and your very lives.
All this havoc, this misfortune, this ruin, descends upon you not from alien foes, but from the one enemy whom you yourselves render as powerful as he is, for whom you go bravely to war, for whose greatness you do not refuse to offer your own bodies unto death. He who thus domineers over you has only two eyes, only two hands, only one body, no more than is possessed by the least man among the infinite numbers dwelling in your cities; he has indeed nothing more than the power that you confer upon him to destroy you.
Where has he acquired enough eyes to spy upon you if you do not provide them yourselves? How can he have so many arms to beat you with if he does not borrow them from you? The feet that trample down your cities, where does he get them if they are not your own? How does he have any power over you except through you? How would he dare assail you if he had not cooperation from you? What could he do to you if you yourselves did not connive with the thief who plunders you, if you were not accomplices of the murderer who kills you, if you were not traitors to yourselves?
You sow your crops in order that he may ravage them; you install and furnish your homes to give him goods to pillage; you rear your daughters that he may gratify his lust; you bring up your children in order that he may confer upon them the greatest privilege he knows — to be led into his battles, to be delivered to butchery, to be made the servants of his greed and the instruments of his vengeance; you yield your bodies unto hard labor in order that he may indulge in his delights and wallow in his filthy pleasures; you weaken yourselves in order to make him the stronger and the mightier to hold you in check. From all these indignities, such as the very beasts of the field would not endure, you can deliver yourselves if you try, not by taking action, but merely by willing to be free.
Resolve to serve no more, and you are at once freed. I do not ask that you place hands upon the tyrant to topple him over, but simply that you support him no longer; then you will behold him, like a great Colossus whose pedestal has been pulled away, fall of his own weight and break into pieces.
This is a very old essay – written in 1577 – but the bulk of it is still as relevant as it was back then. The core points are these:
- Tyrants/rulers always hold sway over a group far vaster than them, such that they could never hope to actually enforce their will over those they wish to dominate if those people simply ignored their authority and refused to obey. (Part I)
- So how do tyrants hold sway over the populace that they could not otherwise control?
- People have a tendency to ideologically naturalize what is now as what has always been, and what must necessarily be, so people are passive and apathetic.
- People tend to follow tradition, so once more than a generation has passed since rule was instituted, most go along with it by default.
- Human beings adapt to, are shaped and molded by, the conditions under which they grow up; when one grows up under tyranny, one becomes so moulded by it that resistence to it is nearly impossible, not least because one doesn't know what liberty was like, and so doesn't know what they're missing out on well enough to fight tooth and nail for it.
- Nobody knows anyone else is discontented, or if they know that, how truly committed they are (because you'd have to know someone's heart of hearts to know that), so we're all locked in – although he didn't put it in these terms – a Prisoner's Dilemma, unable to do anything because we think we're alone.
- Through the classic bread and circuses which distract us from their tyranny, and make us feel as though they're generous even when the wealth they're sharing with us is stolen from us in the first place.
- Through intimidation of the few people who manage to overcome the former points and resist.
- And how does the tyrant get people who are willing to enforce its will? Merely by promising them a share in the spoils, and to abuse people in turn just as they are abused. For some, that is enough.
- However, aligning yourself with tyrants is always a dangerous game, since they're basically inherently unaccountable, being at the top of a hierarchy.
1.15. Ur-Fascism philosophy
A classic text of political philosophy using one of my favorite ideas (the idea of family resemblance). All the more relevant in the modern day.
1.16. Are We Good Enough? - Peter Kropotkin anarchism philosophy
A classic essay responding to a common question about anarchism. I really like this one. Very useful to send to skeptical people!
1.17. Post-Left
1.17.1. A Review of The “Tyranny of Structurelessness”: An organizationalist repudiation of anarchism anarchism
A response to the famous organizationalist essay "The Tyranny of Structurelessness." I was going to write my own, but this one phrases my complains just as well and completely as I would, so I decided to save myself some time and merely mirror this for later reference instead.
All I would add is that a synthesis of the critiques present in the original essay, as flawed as they are, and the responses found in this one is possible, and I think that's to be found in creating explicit "governance documents" even for informal, fluid, affinity based anarchist associations, if they're going to have more than a couple members and stick around for more than a few weeks (which is sometimes necessary, especially when centered around managing material resources), as a way to have a common touchstone for everyone to understand the values, intentions, goals, and processes of the group, to help avoid miscommuncations. The caveats being that such documents need to be:
- collaboratively edited (preferably using something like CryptPad),
- living (open to be changed at any time as norms and needs and context shift, and things are learned from experience),
- designed to be interpreted as a loose statement of common feeling, not legalistically and procedurally interpreted and adhered-to like some sort of Law,
- and the content of which should be explicitly based on things like consensus decision making, direct action, non-hierarchical organization and conflict resolution, drawing lots for different roles, separation, limitation, and enumeration of powers, etc.
1.17.2. Anarchism as a Spiritual Practice anarchism religion
I am not spiritual in the traditional sense. I do not believe in the supernatural, or gods, or goddesses, or enjoy spiritual traditions, practices, or ceremonies, or go on drug trips. I don't adhere to a religion. Insofar as I have a religion (in the broad sense some mystics use it to mean, as in "any set of life practices inspired by a historical tradition that touches on the moral and axiological dimensions of life") then, as this essay says, anarchism is my religion. This essay is a really well-written piece exploring what that means, with some help from philosophical Taoism, which I'm also very sympathetic to.
1.17.3. Bloody Rule and a Cannibal Order! anarchism
A very thorough, in depth, and well-reasoned argument against moralist anarchists from the perspective of a Stirnerite – both that morality is not inevitable from a sort of enlightened egoism, and that it is not necessary to be anarchist.
1.17.4. TODO Communism Unmasked anarchism philosophy
A highly entertaining, very egoist critique of Marxism that shares many of the issues I have with it. Take it with a grain of salt of course, since it isn't the most rigerous out there, but definitely worth at least poking around and reading sections of!
1.17.5. Hayek, Epistemology, and Hegemonic Rationality philosophy anarchism
This is an excellent article about how Hayeks ideas about science and epistemology and information are essentially a post-structualist critique of the idea that we can analyze and understand society scientifically, but argued clearly and in an analytic way. This is essentially a twin of the essay I eventually intend to write showing how late Wittgenstein aligns closely with the anti-essentialism of the post-structuralist philosophers, but in a way that lends a new perspective and argumentative comprehensibility to them.
1.17.6. Natural Law, or Don’t Put a Rubber on Your Willy philosophy anarchism
A very fun egoist anarchist/moral nihilist takedown of the inane logic of natural law. I tried to get natural law to "work" for like four years before I realized no matter what I did it was always totally arbitrary, or collapsed back into egoism, so it's cathartic to read something like this!
1.17.7. The Question of a Stagnant Marxism: Is Marxism Exegetical or Scientific? philosophy
A critique of the dominant Marxist culture (outside acadamia) of being a stagnant, nearly religious exigetical exercise, instead of a dynamic, developing intellectual discipline, from a Marxist (or as he would prefer to be called, a "scientific socialist"). What's funny about this essay is that despite a correct assesment of the problem, there's no analysis of why the problem came to be our really how to solve it – the fundamental ideological, philosophical, and cultural issues that made Marxism the way it is today – and, ironically, it falls into the exact same problems that caused the issue it's pointing out, such as the blinkered monomania with ideological terms (notice how often "dialectical" is prepended to terms unnecessarily in order to make them more Marxist, to the point where the word almost means nothing?), the claiming of "scientificness" for the ideology despite admitting there's very little empiricism, falsificationism, and a very large normative element, and a re-affirmation that any modification or development of core principles or ideas put forward by Marx would be "revisionist" and thus inherently bad and wrong. Thus it is an accurate critique that ultimately demonstrates the problem it's trying to get out of.
1.17.8. The Union of Egoists anarchism philosophy
An in-depth description of and elaboration of a secondary, but extremely useful, concept from Stirner's work, as above, but this time regarding the idea of the "union of egoists." This essay deeply shapes my ideas about how social life and organization should work, or at least how I wish it could.
1.17.9. The Unique and Its Property philosophy
The best translation of Stirner's work to date. I wouldn't necessarily say this book has shaped my ideas, so much as it provides an interesting exploration of ideas that I had already come to by myself (moral nihilism, perspectivism, anti-dogma in all forms) as well as a more consistent and very challenging working-out of them, although I find his arguments, when viewed analytically, as somewhat wanting – hence the essays I intend to write arguing for his positions in a more analytic philosophy way.
1.17.10. Toward the queerest insurrection anarchism queer
A passionate manifesto that I have only felt more as time has gone on speaking out against LGBTQ assimilationism, against the urge to become legible, and speaking to all the ways in which the Queer is at odds inherently with the system we live under. It has deeply influenced how I see what the goals and approaches of queer life and organizing should be.
1.17.11. Post-Left Anarchy anarchism philosophy post_left
Leftism has a continual history of failure – failure to achieve anything, or failure to achieve anything good – and recuperation by capital. Anarchism must reject leftism, even though it was born alongside leftism and shares many of the same ends, and embrace a uniquely anarchist critique of everything leftism stands for: organization, ideology, and morality among them.
1.17.12. Smashing the Orderly Party anarchism
A pretty good summary of all of the core problems that anarchists have with Leninism as an ideology:
- A tendency toward cult of personality and denial of Lenin's historical mistakes
- Vanguardism as an authoritarian, substitutionist, secrative system.
- Marxist and Leninist critiques of the state are never about fundamental problems with it as an institution, with plice, courts, prisons, and the military, but only who is weilding the power (good if it's them, bad if it's anyone else!)
- Socialism is just a form of bureaucratic state capitalism and reformism (see State Socialism and Anarchism by Benjamin Tucker)
1.17.13. Software and Anarchy anarchism programming software
A treatment of various issues in software design and production (including programming tools) from the perspective of an egoist anarchist influenced by Bookchins ideas around social ecology and liberatory technology. This is definitely an interesting piece, although there are specific things I disagree with, such as:
- That a static type system is inherently bad or limiting of the programmer. To make this critique, the authors seem to be conflating static type systems with static programming languages, but you could easily have a language as dynamic as Common Lisp or Smalltalk with a static type system (see Coalton), as well as pointing at the anti-human consequences of non-gradual type systems without realizing that gradual type systems are possible! If those two points are addressed, then, static type systems can be had without them being inherently anti-liberatory, and can provide benefits, by helping you remember and deal with details that'd otherwise be easy to forget or get wrong – an important thing for someone like me who has a memory-related disability!
- The idea that it's a good idea to use a license for your works that is copyleft but also explicitly denies commerical use to all except worker co-operatives, or in peer-production where trade is direct sharing instead of monetary compensation. While at first I found this idea intriguing, because I see licenses not as things that we need to worry about the enforcability of, since the copyright system ultimately always serves corporate interests, and therefore it doesn't matter whether they could theoretically be enforced or not, but instead as statements of intentions and preferences with respect to how your contributions to the Commons should be understood and treated by others, and this seemed like a clear statement of values in support of things I like (peer production and worker ownership), I quickly grew uncomfortable with it upon further thought. Namely because:
- While licenses are in my opinon mostly to be viewed as statements of values and preferences, they also do inherently involve the, at least rhetorical, invocation of state violence. Using the state's legal system to undo copyright itself, to return things to the commons where they should be, if they benefitted in any way from the commons, as copyleft does, doesn't seem like a problem to me, because it's less a positive application of state violence (rhetorically) then a nullification of it. However, this license seems to want to use state violence to militate against certain forms of organization.
- This is especially bad, in my opinion, because I don't think peer production is inherently better than trade for forms of monetary compensation, and I don't think all worker cooperatives are good, or all forms of corporations or wage labor are bad. Especially in the second case, the former is more likely to be less exploitative than the latter, but not necessarily. There are situations in which I can imagine wage labor is just fine, and a small business isn't exploitative, and situations I can imagine in which a worker cooperative is a cesspit of backstabbing, infighting, power politics, and exploitation of people with less voice in the process, and externalities on the community. So I don't see why I should make such an absolute statement.
However overall I agree with and am interested in the conclusions of this paper!
1.17.14. Some Thoughts on the Creative Nothing philosophy
The creative nothing is one of the most interesting, and overtly Taoist, ideas that Stirner has – but it is only explicitly discussed in two places in The Unique and Its Property. More can be inferred about it from applying the rest of Stirner's philosophical attitude to the idea, however, and this article takes up that worthwhile endeavor well, as a useful elaboration on that crucial idea.
1.17.15. Stirner's Critics philosophy
Stirner (in the third person) responds to some criticisms of his philosophical magnum opus. Provides a clearer, shorter, and more accessible elucidation of some of his ideas, and responds preemptively to some critiques one might have. This was my introduction to him, and could well by yours as well!
1.17.16. Critique of "Left-Wing" Culture
1.17.16.1. Transmisogyny transmisogyny
Another horrifically poignant and accurate personal account, from a trans woman on Tumblr, of what it is like to exist in "queer feminist" spaces as someone who's femininity – and thus right to belong, and moral goodness – is constantly fragile and in question.
1.17.16.2. I Am A Transwoman. I Am In The Closet. I Am Not Coming Out. transmisogyny
A painfully personal exposition of a life of gender dysphoria as a closeted trans woman, and using that position as a window into how truly, horribly and damaging the misandry of cis (and some transfem) feminists is. Not just to trans women, but also to cis men, too, but how it also forms a convenient echo chamber through thought-terminating cliches and dismissing messages based on who says them, to insulate feminists from possible criticism and the impacts of their words.
1.17.16.3. Hot Allostatic Load transmisogyny
A trans women's experiences being abused at the hands of queer feminist spaces – transmisogyny, the inherent evil of callout culture and whisper networks, and so on. Just go fucking read it, it's an incredibly powerfully and poignantly written essay that, if you're on the left in the US, will probably deeply challenge your views.
1.17.16.4. How Twitter can ruin a life: Isabel Fall’s complicated story
The story of how Twitter cancel culture essentially killed a trans woman, convincing her that she couldn't truly be a woman, that the newfound identity she'd just been stepping into was invalid and needed to die, and that she should detransition, all because they couldn't handle a provocative title, and didn't read further than that title before banding up into a mob to punish her.
The story repeatedly goes to great lengths to try to say that it somehow wasn't cancel culture, but that's purely an exercise in doublethink. It absolutely is, it bears all the hallmarks of it:
- A preference for paranoid over reparative readings – looking for what's wrong with a work and trying to be angry at that, instead of looking at what's good about a work, possibly even what's good about it that others might appreciate even if you don't.
- Non-marginalized people trying to be social justice warriors on marginalized people's behalf without asking them, for virtue points.
- Thw dynamics of a mob, where nuance is erased and stopping the momentum is impossible.
- Paranoid assumptions about intention.
- The idea that only marginalized people can possibly write about marginalized experiences
- The idea that if someone writes about a marginalized experience differently than you would have, that means they "aren't really X."
- etc.
Some particularly egregious quotes are:
“There were several reporters that reached out to me right after the story came down. I remember having a conversation with one of them and saying, ‘Is [writing about] this really what you want to do? I’m not going to participate. I think that this is just going to make it worse,’” Clarke says. “And they ran with it. It brought in the whole cancel culture thing. Isabel needed that story down for her, not for them, and not for anybody else. But for her. And that’s why it came down. I tried to make that clear [in the editor’s note on the story’s removal]. But people still wanted that cancel narrative.”
Why did Isabel Fall need the story taken down for her own sake, hmm?
And:
"If anybody canceled Isabel Fall, it was Isabel Fall. She remains the subject of her own sentences."
Who made her "cancel herself" – check into the hospital and take down her story and ultimately kill the new version of herself she was stepping into? This is almost victim blaming to protect cancel culture.
1.17.16.5. Shaming Isn’t Shielding: The Moral Panics That Cry Wolf praxis
Despite being framed as specific to the furry community – and one particular kind of social harassment – this is actually a really good general guide, if interpreted more broadly, for spotting many (although not all) kinds of social harassment that aims to take advantage of our desire to be "good," "moral," "protect people," "weed out creeps," and other such instincts. The crux of it is this:
As I mentioned previously, this “Google Doc expose” pattern has been employed in the past by actual victims desperate for their community to stop supporting their abuser.
Sometimes, when you see a Google Doc floating around accusing a furry of being abusive, that’s what you’re seeing.
Other times, you’re being handed a specially crafted piece of rhetoric that cherry-picks and lies by omission to make innocent people seem guilty of being terrible.
Here are a few things to watch out for to distinguish legitimate grievances from targeted harassment.
- Scope creep.
- Is the doc focused on a specific, focused group of people, or does it read like a hit piece on as many popular furries as possible?
- Actions, not affiliations.
- A legitimate call-out will focus on what harmful actions a person did, their victims’ stories, and the harms caused as a result of said actions.
- Harassment docs focus on weak ties (“they were in the same Telegram group as ____”) or a person’s interests.
- Past remediation efforts.
- Did the person in question immediately jump to the Google Doc outcome without trying anything else first?
- What are the incentives involved?
- Speaking out about a horrible experience is terrifying, especially if it was perpetrated by someone with a lot of wealth or social capital in your community.
- Conversely, trying to guilt the offending party or their audience into donating money to buy silence is simply blackmail.
- Is this part of a larger pattern?
- Is this the only callout a person has ever made?
- Is this the tenth callout this person has made this year?
- What other metadata can you use to judge the validity of the information you’re presented with?
This short list of things to look out for isn’t foolproof, but it should help most people reduce their error rate for assessing a callout on social media.
1.17.16.6. Fandom, purity culture, and the rise of the anti-fan
A story of how purity culture took over online spaces.
1.17.16.7. Post-Left vs “Woke” Left anarchism post_left
The woke left fears the individualist/egoist post-left, because it offers something so much stonger, more vital, more free, than it ever could. This is a takedown of many of the ways in which it tries to smear egoists to protect its precious "correct" church of anarchism or leftism.
1.17.16.8. The “Stirner Wasn’t A Capitalist You Fucking Idiot” Cheat Sheet philosophy anarchism
Stirner is often accused of being somehow antithetical in principles, values, and tendencies to anarchism. This is bullshit. This will show you why.
1.17.16.9. Vampire Castle post_left
This essay has aged poorly in one, narrow sense — in that the particular figure Fisher chose to defend, Russell Brand, has shown himself to be an asshole in a multilayered, ongoing way since the time of writing. But Fisher was not Brand, and for every person like Brand whom the left accurately identifies as a problem, there are an equal number whom they slander for no reason; and that isn't even what's important about this essay. Many of the core ideas behind this essay are evergreen, and truer now than when it was written.
Insights:
- "The petit bourgeoisie which dominates the academy and the culture industry has all kinds of subtle deflections and pre-emptions which prevent [class] even coming up, and then, if it does come up, they make one think it is a terrible impertinence…"
- "[T]he features of the discourses and the desires which have led us to this grim and demoralising pass, where class has disappeared, but moralism is everywhere, where solidarity is impossible, but guilt and fear are omnipresent" are "we have allowed bourgeois modes of subjectivity to contaminate our movement". Namely:
- The Vampire Castle:
- "The Vampires’ Castle specialises in propagating guilt. It is driven by a priest’s desire to excommunicate and condemn, an academic-pedant’s desire to be the first to be seen to spot a mistake, and a hipster’s desire to be one of the in-crowd."
- "The danger in attacking the Vampires’ Castle is that it can look as if – and it will do everything it can to reinforce this thought – that one is also attacking the struggles against racism, sexism, heterosexism. But, far from being the only legitimate expression of such struggles, the Vampires’ Castle is best understood as a bourgeois-liberal perversion and appropriation of the energy of these movements"
- "rather than seeking a world in which everyone achieves freedom from identitarian classification, the Vampires’ Castle seeks to corral people back into identi-camps, where they are forever defined in the terms set by dominant power, crippled by self-consciousness and isolated by a logic of solipsism which insists that we cannot understand one another unless we belong to the same identity group."
- "I’ve noticed a fascinating magical inversion projection-disavowal mechanism whereby the sheer mention of class is now automatically treated as if that means one is trying to downgrade the importance of race and gender. In fact, the exact opposite is the case, as the Vampires’ Castle uses an ultimately liberal understanding of race and gender to obfuscate class. […] it [is] noticeable that the discussion of class privilege [is] entirely absent."
- "The problem that the Vampires’ Castle was set up to solve is this: how do you hold immense wealth and power while also appearing as a victim, marginal and oppositional? The solution was already there – in the Christian Church. So the VC has recourse to all the infernal strategies, dark pathologies and psychological torture instruments Christianity invented, and which Nietzsche described in The Genealogy of Morals. This priesthood of bad conscience, this nest of pious guilt-mongers, is exactly what Nietzsche predicted when he said that something worse than Christianity was already on the way. Now, here it is …"
- "The Vampires’ Castle feeds on the energy and anxieties and vulnerabilities of young students, but most of all it lives by converting the suffering of particular groups – the more ‘marginal’ the better – into academic capital. The most lauded figures in the Vampires’ Castle are those who have spotted a new market in suffering […]"
- "The first law of the Vampires’ Castle is: individualise and privatise everything. While in theory it claims to be in favour of structural critique, in practice it never focuses on anything except individual behaviour."
- "Because they are petit-bourgeois to the core, the members of the Vampires’ Castle are intensely competitive, but this is repressed in the passive aggressive manner typical of the bourgeoisie. What holds them together is not solidarity, but mutual fear – the fear that they will be the next one to be outed, exposed, condemned."
- "The third law of the Vampires’ Castle is: propagate as much guilt as you can. The more guilt the better. People must feel bad: it is a sign that they understand the gravity of things. It’s OK to be class-privileged if you feel guilty about privilege and make others in a subordinate class position to you feel guilty too. You do some good works for the poor, too, right?"
- "The fourth law of the Vampires’ Castle is: essentialize. While fluidity of identity, pluraity and multiplicity are always claimed on behalf of the VC members […] the enemy is always to be essentialized. Since the desires animating the VC are in large part priests’ desires to excommunicate and condemn, there has to be a strong distinction between Good and Evil, with the latter essentialized. Notice the tactics. X has made a remark/ has behaved in a particular way – these remarks/ this behaviour might be construed as transphobic/ sexist etc. So far, OK. But it’s the next move which is the kicker. X then becomes defined as a transphobe/ sexist etc. Their whole identity becomes defined by one ill-judged remark or behavioural slip."
- "The fifth law of the Vampires’ Castle: think like a liberal (because you are one). The VC’s work of constantly stoking up reactive outrage consists of endlessly pointing out the screamingly obvious: capital behaves like capital (it’s not very nice!), repressive state apparatuses are repressive. We must protest!"
- Neo-Anarachism (this is the one I most fall afoul of, although I'm neither bourgoise nor educated technically, that is the culture I was raised in/am closest to; and although I think I have good reasons for my lack of action — namely, being very disabled — that doesn't change the effects): "By neo-anarchists I definitely do not mean anarchists or syndicalists involved in actual workplace organisation, such as the Solidarity Federation. I mean, rather, those who identify as anarchists but whose involvement in politics extends little beyond student protests and occupations, and commenting on Twitter. Like the denizens of the Vampires’ Castle, neo-anarchists usually come from a petit-bourgeois background, if not from somewhere even more class-privileged […] They are also overwhelmingly young: in their twenties or at most their early thirties, and what informs the neo-anarchist position is a narrow historical horizon."
- "Neo-anarchists have experienced nothing but capitalist realism. […] But the problem with neo-anarchism is that it unthinkingly reflects this historical moment rather than offering any escape from it. It forgets, or perhaps is genuinely unaware of, the Labour Party’s role in nationalising major industries and utilities or founding the National Health Service. Neo-anarchists will assert that ‘parliamentary politics never changed anything’, or the ‘Labour Party was always useless’ while attending protests about the NHS, or retweeting complaints about the dismantling of what remains of the welfare state. media to attempt to engineer change from there. […] Purism shades into fatalism; better not to be in any way tainted by the corruption of the mainstream, better to uselessly ‘resist’ than to risk getting your hands dirty."
- "It’s not surprising, then, that so many neo-anarchists come across as depressed. This depression is no doubt reinforced by the anxieties of postgraduate life, since, like the Vampires’ Castle, neo-anarchism has its natural home in universities, and is usually propagated by those studying for postgraduate qualifications, or those who have recently graduated from such study."
- "Why have these two configurations come to the fore?"
- "they have been allowed to prosper by capital because they serve its interests. […] why would capital be concerned about a ‘left’ that replaces class politics with a moralising individualism, and that, far from building solidarity, spreads fear and insecurity?"
- "It might have been possible to ignore the Vampires’ Castle and the neo-anarchists if it weren’t for capitalist cyberspace. The VC’s pious moralising has been a feature of a certain ‘left’ for many years – but, if one wasn’t a member of this particular church, its sermons could be avoided. Social media means that this is no longer the case, and there is little protection from the psychic pathologies propagated by these discourses."
- "The bourgeois-identitarian left knows how to propagate guilt and conduct a witch hunt, but it doesn’t know how to make converts. But that, after all, is not the point. The aim is not to popularise a leftist position, or to win people over to it, but to remain in a position of elite superiority, but now with class superiority redoubled by moral superiority too. ‘How dare you talk – it’s we who speak for those who suffer!’"
- The Vampire Castle:
- "What is to be done?"
- "So what can we do now? First of all, it is imperative to reject identitarianism, and to recognise that there are no identities, only desires, interests and identifications. […] Sadly, the right act on this insight more effectively than the left does."
- "But the rejection of identitarianism can only be achieved by the re-assertion of class. A left that does not have class at its core can only be a liberal pressure group. Class consciousness is always double: it involves a simultaneous knowledge of the way in which class frames and shapes all experience, and a knowledge of the particular position that we occupy in the class structure."
- "It must be remembered that the aim of our struggle is not recognition by the bourgeoisie, nor even the destruction of the bourgeoisie itself. It is the class structure – a structure that wounds everyone, even those who materially profit from it – that must be destroyed."
- "The interests of the working class are the interests of all; the interests of the bourgeoisie are the interests of capital, which are the interests of no-one. Our struggle must be towards the construction of a new and surprising world, not the preservation of identities shaped and distorted by capital."
1.17.16.10. Anarchism and the politics of ressentiment anarchism post_left
Nietzsche sees anarchism as poisoned at the root by the pestiferous weed of ressentiment — the spiteful politics of the weak and pitiful, the morality of the slave. Is Nietzsche here merely venting his conservative wrath against radical politics, or is he diagnosing a real sickness that has infected our radical political imaginary? Despite the Nietzsche’s obvious prejudice towards radical politics, this paper will take seriously his charge against anarchism…
[…]
For Nietzsche, the way we interpret and impose values on the world has a history — its origins are often brutal and far removed from the values they produce. The value of ‘good’, for instance, was invented by the noble and high-placed to apply to themselves, in contrast to common, low-placed and plebeian.[3] It was the value of the master — ‘good’ — as opposed to that of the slave — ‘bad’. Thus, according to Nietzsche, it was in this pathos of distance, between the high-born and the low-born, this absolute sense of superiority, that values were created.
However, this equation of good and aristocratic began to be undermined by a slave revolt in values. […] the slave revolt in morality inverted the noble system of values and began to equate good with the lowly, the powerless — the slave. This inversion introduced the pernicious spirit of revenge and hatred into the creation of values. Therefore morality, as we understand it, had its roots in this vengeful will to power of the powerless over the powerful — the revolt of the slave against the master. It was from this imperceptible, subterranean hatred that grew the values subsequently associated with the good — pity, altruism, meekness, etc.
Political values also grew from this poisonous root. For Nietzsche, values of equality and democracy, which form the cornerstone of radical political theory, arose out of the slave revolt in morality. They are generated by the same spirit of revenge and hatred of the powerful. […] Anarchism is for Nietzsche the most extreme heir to democratic values […] It seeks to level the differences between individuals, to abolish class distinctions, to raze hierarchies to the ground, and to equalize the powerful and the powerless, the rich and the poor, the master and the slave. To Nietzsche this is bringing everything down to level of the lowest common denominator — to erase the pathos of distance between the master and slave, the sense of difference and superiority through which great values are created…
Slave morality is characterized by the attitude of ressentiment — the resentment and hatred of the powerless for the powerful. Nietzsche sees ressentiment as an entirely negative sentiment — the attitude of denying what is life-affirming, saying ‘no’ to what is different, what is ‘outside’ or ‘other’. Ressentiment is characterized by an orientation to the outside, rather than the focus of noble morality, which is on the self.[7] While the master says ‘I am good’ and adds as an afterthought, ‘therefore he is bad’; the slave says the opposite — ‘He (the master) is bad, therefore I am good’. […] Nietzsche says: “… in order to come about, slave morality first has to have an opposing, external world, it needs, psychologically speaking, external stimuli in order to act all, — its action is basically a reaction.”[8] This reactive stance, this inability to define anything except in opposition to something else, is the attitude of ressentiment. It is the reactive stance of the weak who define themselves in opposition to the strong. The weak need the existence of this external enemy to identify themselves as ‘good’. […] The man of ressentiment hates the noble with an intense spite, a deep-seated, seething hatred and jealousy…
Is anarchism a political expression of ressentiment? Is it poisoned by a deep hatred of the powerful? […]
Anarchism as a revolutionary political philosophy has many different voices, origins and interpretations. […] These are united, however, by a fundamental rejection and critique of political authority in all its forms. The critique of political authority — the conviction that power is oppressive, exploitative and dehumanizing — may be said to be the crucial politico-ethical standpoint of anarchism. […] The State is the main target of the anarchist critique of authority. It is for anarchists the fundamental oppression in society…
[T]he State, for anarchists, is a priori oppression, no matter what form it takes. […] The State has its own impersonal logic, its own momentum, its own priorities […] As an abstract machine of domination, the State haunts different class actualizations — not just the bourgeoisie State, but the worker’s State too. […] This conception of the State ironically strikes a familiar note with Nietzsche.
Anarchism is based on an essentially optimistic conception of human nature: if individuals have a natural tendency to get on well together then there is no need for the existence of a State to arbitrate between them. […] Anarchism may be understood as a struggle between natural authority and artificial authority. Anarchists do not reject all forms of authority, as the old cliché would have it. On the contrary, they declare their absolute obedience to the authority embodied in what Bakunin calls ‘natural laws’. Natural laws are essential to Man’s existence according to Bakunin — they surround us, shape us and determine the physical world in which we live.[24] However this is not a form of slavery because these laws are not external to man… They are, on the contrary, what constitute man — they are his essence. […] Anarchism, then, is based on a specific notion of human essence. Morality has its basis in human nature, not in any external source.
Natural authority is implacably opposed to “artificial authority.” By artificial authority Bakunin means power […] This power is external to human nature and an imposition upon it. It stultifies the development of humanity’s innate moral characteristics and intellectual capacities.
In this critique of political authority, power (artificial authority) is external to the human subject. The human subject is oppressed by this power, but remains uncontaminated by it because human subjectivity is a creation of a natural, as opposed to a political, system. Thus anarchism is based on a clear, Manichean division between artificial and natural authority, between power and subjectivity, between State and society. Furthermore political authority is fundamentally repressive and destructive of man’s potential. Human society, argue the anarchists, cannot develop until the institutions and laws which keep it in ignorance and servitude, until the fetters which bind it, are thrown off.
[…]
Anarchism operates within a Manichean political logic: it creates an essential, moral opposition between society and the State, between humanity and power. […] This logic […] is the central feature of Manichean thought.
[…]
Opposing living sociability to the State, in the same way that Marxism opposed the proletariat to capitalism, suggests that anarchism was unable to transcend the traditional political categories which bound Marxism. […] Manicheism […] is the undercurrent that runs through [all these theories] and circumscribes them. […] as long as there is an enemy to destroy and a subject who will destroy it; as long as there is the promise of the final battle and final victory. […] This is the binary, dialectical logic that pervades anarchism: the place of power — the State — must be overthrown by the essential human subject, the pure subject of resistance. Anarchism ‘essentializes’ the very power it opposes.
Manichean logic thus involves a reverse mirroring operation: the place of resistance is a reflection, in reverse, of the place of power. In the case of anarchism, human subjectivity is essentially moral and rational while the State is essentially immoral and irrational.[38] The State is essential to the existence of revolutionary subject, just as the revolutionary subject is essential to the existence of the State. One defines itself in opposition to the other. The purity of revolutionary identity is only defined in contrast to the impurity of political power. […]
[…] although there are differences, the Manichean relationship of opposition between the human subject and political power that is found in anarchism obeys the general logic of ressentiment described above. This is for two reasons.
- Firstly, as we have seen, ressentiment is based on the moral prejudice of the powerless against the powerful — the revolt of the ‘slave’ against the ‘master’. We can see this moral opposition to power clearly in anarchist discourse […]
- Secondly, ressentiment is characterized by the fundamental need to identify oneself by looking outwards and in opposition towards an external enemy. […] Anarchism subscribes to a dialectical logic, according to which the human species emerges from an ‘animal-like’ state, and begins to develop innate moral and rational faculties in a natural system.[40] However […] the subject cannot achieve his full human identity as long as he remains oppressed by the State. […] The realization of the subject is always stultified, deferred, put off, by the State. This dialectic of Man and State suggests that the identity of the subject is characterized as essentially ‘rational’ and ‘moral’ only in so far as the unfolding of these innate faculties and qualities is prevented by the State. Paradoxically the State, which is seen by anarchists as an obstacle to the full identity of man, is, at the same time, essential to the formation of this incomplete identity. Without this stultifying oppression, the anarchist subject would be unable to see itself as ‘moral’ and ‘rational’. His identity is thus complete in its incompleteness.
So the Manicheism that inhabits anarchist discourse is a logic of ressentiment that for Nietzsche is a distinctly unhealthy outlook, emanating from a position of weakness and sickness. Revolutionary identity in anarchist philosophy is constituted through its essential opposition to power. […] But is it?
Bakunin himself throws some doubts on this when he talks about the power principle. This is the natural lust for power which Bakunin believes is innate in every individual […] The power principle [is /why/] man cannot be trusted with power […] he has perhaps unconsciously exposed the hidden contradiction that lies at the heart of anarchist discourse: namely that, while anarchism bases itself upon a notion of an essential human subjectivity uncontaminated by power, this subjectivity is ultimately impossible. Pure revolutionary identity is torn apart, subverted by a ‘natural’ desire for power, the lack at the heart of every individual. […] Kropotkin, too, talks about the desire for power and authority. […] If this is the case, can human essence still be seen as unpolluted by power? While anarchism’s notion of subjectivity is not entirely undermined by this contradiction, it is nevertheless destabilized by it: it is made ambiguous and incomplete. It forces one to question anarchism’s notion of a revolution of humanity against power: if humans have an essential desire for power, then how can one be sure that a revolution aimed at destroying power will not turn into a revolution aimed at capturing power?
Has anarchism as a political and social theory of revolution been invalidated because of the contradictions in its conception of human subjectivity? […] I would argue that anarchism, if it can free itself from these essentialist and Manichean categories, can overcome the ressentiment that poisons and limits it. Classical anarchism is a politics of ressentiment because it seeks to overcome power. It sees power as evil, destructive, something that stultifies the full realization of the individual. […] However I have shown that this separation between the individual and power is itself unstable and threatened by a ‘natural’ desire for power — the power principle. Nietzsche would argue that this desire for power — will to power — is indeed ‘natural’, and it is the suppression of this desire that has had such a debilitating effect on man, turning him against himself and producing an attitude of ressentiment.
However perhaps one could argue that this desire for power in man is produced precisely through attempts to deny or extinguish relations of power in the ‘natural order’. Perhaps power may be seen in terms of the Lacanian Real — as that irrepressible lack that cannot be symbolized, and which always returns to haunt the symbolic order, disrupting any attempt by the subject to form a complete identity. […] Anarchism attempts to complete the identity of the subject by separating him, in an absolute Manichean sense, from the world of power. […] However, as we have seen, this world free of power is jeopardized by the desire for power latent in every individual. The more anarchism tries to free society from relations of power, the more it remains paradoxically caught up in power. Power here has returned as the real that haunts all attempts to free the world of power. […] the attempts to deny power, through essentialist concepts of ‘natural’ laws and ‘natural’ morality, themselves constitute power, or at least are conditioned by relations of power. These essentialist identities and categories cannot be imposed without the radical exclusion of other identities. This exclusion is an act of power. If one attempts to radically exclude power, as the anarchists did, power ‘returns’ precisely in the structures of exclusion themselves.
[…] So how does anarchism overcome this ressentiment that has shown to be so self destructive and life-denying? By positively affirming power, rather than denying it — to ‘say yes’ to power, as Nietzsche would put it. It is only by affirming power, by acknowledging that we come from the same world as power, not from a ‘natural’ world removed from it, and that we can never be entirely free from relations of power, that one can engage in politically-relevant strategies of resistance against power. This does not mean, of course, that anarchism should lay down its arms and embrace the State and political authority. On the contrary, anarchism can more effectively counter political domination by engaging with, rather than denying, power.
To use Michel Foucault’s definition, power is a “mode of action upon the action of others.”[46] Power is merely the effect of one’s actions upon the actions of another. Power […] is merely a relationship of forces, forces that flow between different actors and throughout our everyday actions. […] For instance, rational and moral discourses, which anarchists saw as innocent of power and as weapons in the struggle against power, are themselves constituted by power relations […] Power in this sense is productive rather than repressive. It is therefore senseless and indeed impossible to try to construct, as anarchists do, a world outside power.
However, just because one can never be free from power does not mean that one can never be free from domination. […] For Foucault, relations of power become relations of domination when the free and unstable flow of power relations becomes blocked and congealed — when it […] no longer allows reciprocal relationships. […] The State, according to Foucault, is merely an assemblage of different power relations that have become congealed in this way. […] While anarchists see power as emanating from the State, Foucault sees the State as emanating from power. The State, in other words, is merely an effect of power relations that have crystallized into relations of domination.
[…] [T]he point of this distinction is to show that this essential separation is now impossible. Domination — oppressive political institutions like the State — now comes from the same world as power. In other words it disrupts the strict Manichean separation of society and power. Anarchism and indeed radical politics generally, cannot remain in this comfortable illusion that we as political subjects, are somehow not complicit in the very regime that oppresses us. […] As political subjects we can never relax and hide behind essentialist identities and Manichean structures […] Rather we must be constantly on our guard against the possibility of domination.
[…] One can, as I have argued, never hope to overcome power completely — because every overcoming is itself the imposition of another regime of power. The best that can be hoped for is a reorganization of power relations — through struggle and resistance — in ways that are less oppressive and dominating. Domination can therefore be minimized by acknowledging our inevitable involvement with power, not by attempting to place ourselves impossibly outside the world of power.
This definition of power that I have constructed — as an unstable and free-flowing relation dispersed throughout the social network — may be seen as a non-ressentiment notion of power. […] To overcome ressentiment we must, in other words, will power. We must affirm a will to power — in the form of creative, life-affirming values, according to Nietzsche.[56] This is to accept the notion of self-overcoming’.[57] To ‘overcome’ oneself in this sense, would mean an overcoming of the essentialist identities and categories that limit us.
[…]
I would argue that anarchism would be greatly enhanced as a political and ethical philosophy if it eschewed essentialist categories, leaving itself open to different and contingent identities — a post-anarchism. To affirm difference and contingency would be to become a philosophy of the strong, rather than the weak. Nietzsche exhorts us to ‘live dangerously’, to do away with certainties, to break with essences and structures, and to embrace uncertainty. “Build your cities on the slopes of Vesuvius! Send your ships into unchartered seas!” he says.[60] The politics of resistance against domination must take place in a world without guarantees. To remain open to difference and contingency, to affirm the eternal return of power, would be to become what Nietzsche calls the superman or Overman.
[…]
Perhaps anarchism could become a new ‘heroic’ philosophy, which is no longer reactive but, rather, creates values.
[…]
Furthermore, perhaps one could envisage a form of political community or collective identity that did not restrict difference. The question of community is central to radical politics, including anarchism. One cannot talk about collective action without at least posing the question of community. For Nietzsche, most modern radical aspirations towards community were a manifestation of the ‘herd’ mentality. However it may be possible to construct a ressentiment-free notion of community from Nietzsche’s own concept of power. For Nietzsche, active power is the individual’s instinctive discharge of his forces and capacities which produces in him an enhanced sensation of power, while reactive power, as we have seen, needs an external object to act on and define itself in opposition to.[66] Perhaps one could imagine a form of community based on active power. For Nietzsche this enhanced feeling of power may be derived from assistance and benevolence towards others, from enhancing the feeling of power of others.[67] Like the ethics of mutual aid, a community based on will to power may be composed of a series of inter-subjective relations that involve helping and caring for people without dominating them and denying difference.
1.17.16.11. Why Has Critique Run out of Steam? From Matters of Fact to Matters of Concern critical_theory
Does philosophical critique often feel destructive, and cynically unbeatable? Do you feel unease seeing the same kinds of tactics that we often see critical philosophers use levelled against such things as vaccines, 9/11, trans healthcare, and climate change — talking about the uncertainty and socially constructed, institutional, incentive, ideologically-driven nature of science, or the profit motives and material incentives on the part of doctors and the pharmacutical industry that might construct something like the belief that transitioning medically should be a common treatment for trans people — that we feel aren't meant to be analyzed that way? This essay gets at the heart of this problem, and suggests a way forward, without falling into reactionary anti-criticism.
What has become of critique, I wonder, when an editorial in the New York Times contains the following quote?
"Most scientists believe that [global] warming is caused largely by man-made pollutants that require strict regulation. Mr. Luntz [a Republican strategist] seems to acknowledge as much when he says that “the scientific debate is closing against us.” His advice, however, is to emphasize that the evidence is not complete.
“Should the public come to believe that the scientific issues are settled,” he writes, “their views about global warming will change accordingly. Therefore, you need to continue to make the lack of scientific certainty a primary issue.”"
…
Do you see why I am worried? I myself have spent some time in the past trying to show “the lack of scientific certainty” inherent in the construction of facts. I too made it a “primary issue.” But I did not exactly aim at fooling the public by obscuring the certainty of a closed argument—or did I? After all, I have been accused of just that sin. … Was I foolishly mistaken? Have things changed so fast?
In which case the danger would no longer be coming from an excessive confidence in ideological arguments posturing as matters of fact—as we have learned to combat so efficiently in the past—but from an excessive distrust of good matters of fact disguised as bad ideological biases! … And yet entire Ph.D. programs are still running to make sure that good American kids are learning the hard way that facts are made up, that there is no such thing as natural, unmediated, unbiased access to truth, that we are always prisoners of language, that we always speak from a particular standpoint, and so on, while dangerous extremists are using the very same argument of social construction to destroy hard-won evidence that could save our lives. … Why does it burn my tongue to say that global warming is a fact whether you like it or not? Why can’t I simply say that the argument is closed for good?
… what does it mean when this lack of sure ground is taken away from us by the worst possible fellows as an argument against the things we cherish?
…
What has critique become when a French general, no, a marshal of critique, namely, Jean Baudrillard, claims in a published book that the Twin Towers destroyed themselves under their own weight, so to speak, undermined by the utter nihilism inherent in capitalism itself—as if the terrorist planes were pulled to suicide by the powerful attraction of this black hole of nothingness?
What has become of critique when my neighbor in the little Bourbonnais village where I live looks down on me as someone hopelessly naïve because I believe that the United States had been attacked by terrorists? … I am now the one who naïvely believes in some facts because I am educated …
What has become of critique when someone as eminent as Stanley Fish … believes he defends science studies, my field, by comparing the laws of physics to the rules of baseball?7
What has become of critique when there is a whole industry denying that the Apollo program landed on the moon?
What has become of critique when DARPA uses for its Total Information Awareness project the Baconian slogan Scientia est potentia? Didn’t I read that somewhere in Michel Foucault? Has knowledge-slash-power been co-opted of late by the National Security Agency? Has Discipline and Punish become the bedtime reading of Mr. Ridge (fig. 1)?
Let me be mean for a second. What’s the real difference between conspiracists and a popularized, that is a teachable version of social critique inspired by a too quick reading …? In both cases, you have to learn to become suspicious of everything people say because of course we all know that they live in the thralls of a complete illusion of their real motives. Then, after disbelief has struck and an explanation is requested for what is really going on, in both cases again it is the same appeal to powerful agents hidden in the dark acting always consistently, continuously, relentlessly. Of course, we in the academy like to use more elevated causes—society, discourse, knowledge-slash power, fields of forces, empires, capitalism—while conspiracists like to portray a miserable bunch of greedy people with dark intents, but I find something troublingly similar … it worries me to detect, in those mad mixtures of knee-jerk disbelief, punctilious demands for proofs, and free use of powerful explanation from the social neverland many of the weapons of social critique. Of course conspiracy theories are an absurd deformation of our own arguments, but, like weapons smuggled through a fuzzy border to the wrong party, these are our weapons nonetheless.
… have we behaved like mad scientists who have let the virus of critique out of the confines of their laboratories and cannot do anything now to limit its deleterious effects: it mutates now, gnawing everything up, even the vessels in which it is contained? …
If the dense and moralist cigar-smoking reactionary bourgeois can transform him-or herself into a freefloating agnostic bohemian, moving opinions, capital, and networks from one end of the planet to the other without attachment, why would he or she not be able to absorb the most sophisticated tools of deconstruction, social construction, discourse analysis, postmodernism, postology?
We can summarize, I estimate, 90 percent of the contemporary critical scene by the following series of diagrams that fixate the object at only two positions, what I have called the fact position and the fairy position—fact and fairy are etymologically related but I won’t develop this point here. The fairy position is very well known and is used over and over again by many social scientists who associate criticism with antifetishism. The role of the critic is then to show that what the naïve believers are doing with objects is simply a projection of their wishes onto a material entity that does nothing at all by itself. Here they have diverted to their petty use the prophetic fulmination against idols “they have mouths and speak not, they have ears and hear not,” but they use this prophecy to decry the very objects of belief—gods, fashion, poetry, sport, desire, you name it—to which naïve believers cling with so much intensity.22 And then the courageous critic, who alone remains aware and attentive, who never sleeps, turns those false objects into fetishes that are supposed to be nothing but mere empty white screens on which is projected the power of society, domination, whatever. The naïve believer has received a first salvo (fig. 2).
But, wait, a second salvo is in the offing, and this time it comes from the fact pole. This time it is the poor bloke, again taken aback, whose behavior is now “explained” by the powerful effects of indisputable matters of fact: “You, ordinary fetishists, believe you are free but, in reality, you are acted on by forces you are not conscious of. Look at them, look, you blind idiot” (and here you insert whichever pet facts the social scientists fancy to work with, taking them from economic infrastructure, fields of discourse, social domination, race, class, and gender, maybe throwing in some neurobiology, evolutionary psychology, whatever, provided they act as indisputable facts whose origin, fabrication, mode of development are left unexamined) (fig. 3).
Do you see now why it feels so good to be a critical mind? Why critique, this most ambiguous pharmakon, has become such a potent euphoric drug? You are always right! When naive believers are clinging forcefully to their objects, claiming that they are made to do things because of their gods, their poetry, their cherished objects, you can turn all of those attachments into so many fetishes and humiliate all the believers by showing that it is nothing but their own projection, that you, yes you alone, can see. But as soon as naive believers are thus inflated by some belief in their own importance, in their own projective capacity, you strike them by a second uppercut and humiliate them again, this time by showing that, whatever they think, their behavior is entirely determined by the action of powerful causalities coming from objective reality they don’t see, but that you, yes you, the never sleeping critic, alone can see. Isn’t this fabulous? Isn’t it really worth going to graduate school to study critique? “Enter here, you poor folks. After arduous years of reading turgid prose, you will be always right, you will never be taken in any more; no one, no matter how powerful, will be able to accuse you of naivete, that supreme sin, any longer? Better equipped than Zeus himself you rule alone, striking from above with the salvo of antifetishism in one hand and the solid causality of objectivity in the other.” The only loser is the naive believer, the great unwashed, always caught off balance (fig. 4).
… The whole rather poor trick that allows critique to go on, although we would never confine our own valuables to their sordid pawnshop, is that there is never any crossover between the two lists of objects in the fact position and the fairy position. …
… What social scientists do to our favorite objects is so horrific that certainly we don’t want them to come any nearer. …
I am not trying to reverse course, to become reactionary, to regret what I have done, to swear that I will never be a constructivist any more. I simply want to … retest the linkages between the new threats [we have] to face and the equipment and training [we] have in order to meet them-and, if necessary, to revise from scratch the whole paraphernalia.
… the critical mind, if it is to renew itself and be relevant again, is to be found in the cultivation of a stubbornly realist attitude—to speak like William James—but a realism dealing with what I will call matters of concern, not matters of fact. The mistake we made, the mistake I made, was to believe that there was no efficient way to criticize matters of fact except by moving away from them and directing one’s attention toward the conditions that made them possible. … This was remaining too faithful to the unfortunate solution inherited from the philosophy of Immanuel Kant. Critique has not been critical enough in spite of all its sore-scratching. Reality is not defined by matters of fact. Matters of fact are not all that is given in experience. Matters of fact are only very partial and … very political renderings of matters of concern and only a subset of what could also be called states of affairs. It is this second empiricism, this return to the realist attitude, that I’d like to offer as the next task for the critically minded.
To indicate the direction of the argument, I want to show that while the Enlightenment profited largely from the disposition of a very powerful descriptive tool, that of matters of fact, which were excellent for debunking quite a lot of beliefs, powers, and illusions, it found itself totally disarmed once matters of fact, in turn, were eaten up by the same debunking impetus. After that, the lights of the Enlightenment were slowly turned off, and some sort of darkness appears to have fallen on campuses. My question is thus: Can we devise another powerful descriptive tool that deals this time with matters of concern and whose import then will no longer be to debunk but to protect and to care, as Donna Haraway would put it?
To retrieve a realist attitude, it is not enough to dismantle critical weapons so uncritically built up by our predecessors as we would obsolete but still dangerous atomic silos. … What set Whitehead completely apart and straight on our path is that he considered matters of fact to be a very poor rendering of what is given in experience and something that muddles entirely the question, What is there? with the question, How do we know it? Those who now mock his philosophy don’t understand that they have resigned themselves to what he called the “bifurcation of nature. They have entirely forgotten what it would require if we were to take this incredible sentence seriously: “*For natural philosophy everything perceived is in nature. We may not pick up and choose. For us the red glow of the sunset should be as much part of nature as are the molecules and electric waves by which men of science would explain the phenomenon*” (CN, pp. 28- 29).
It is not the case that there would exist solid matters of fact and that the next step would be for us to decide whether they will be used to explain something. It is not the case either that the other solution is to attack, criticize, expose, historicize those matters of fact, to show that they are made up, interpreted, flexible.
The critic is not the one who debunks, but the one who assembles. The critic is not the one who lifts the rugs from under the feet of the naive believers, but the one who offers the participants arenas in which to gather. The critic is not the one who alternates haphazardly between antifetishism and positivism like the drunk iconoclast drawn by Goya, but the one for whom, if something is constructed, then it means it is fragile and thus in great need of care and caution. … Critical theory died away long ago; can we become critical again, in the sense here offered by Turing? That is, generating more ideas than we have received, inheriting from a prestigious critical tradition but not letting it die away, or “dropping into quiescence” like a piano no longer struck?
1.17.16.12. What’s the harm in reading? culture
Whereas the other article I mirrored here focuses more on the author, this article is a much better meta-level critique of the sociopsychological dynamics at play in what happened, from an almost post-left anti-moralist perspective:
The violent and oftentimes ironically ignorant backlash against Fall’s story sheds light on a troublingly regressive, entitled, and puritanical trend in the relationship between artists and their audiences […] Readers appear to feel a need to cast their objections to fiction in moral terms, positioning themselves as protectors of the downtrodden. […] in such a way of thinking, art is not a sensual or aesthetic experience but a strictly moral one, its every instance either fundamentally good or evil. […]
That someone reacts with hurt to art doesn’t make that art dangerous, and claiming that all art that’s capable of causing pain is inherently toxic is a solipsistic nightmare in which a reader’s personal experience becomes an act of violence committed against them by an author whom they likely do not know. It’s a reflexive model of critique, a rejection of evaluating art on its own merits. In a way it takes the place of criticism entirely, ignoring aesthetic concerns in favor of moral ones. Perhaps in that emotional reaction is some trace of readers reliving their own trauma and […] reimagining it as a scenario in which they can stop that violation from happening. […] [this] locks us in memories of our own pain and reduces art to something strictly individual, cutting away its ability to let us experience the lives and dreams of people we’ll never know.
Stories like “Attack Helicopter” are vital to unpacking the webs of intersecting forces which make up every human consciousness. They constitute an outlet for the suffering of marginalized artists raised in bigoted, imperialist cultures, a way to process the poison we’re spoon-fed from birth into something that awakens and lays bare. Calls for the destruction or censorship of such stories constitute a rejection of life’s intrinsic complexity, a retreat into the black and white moral absolutism of adolescence, or theocracy. These rigid moral strictures strip marginalized communities of their full humanity and of their history as makers of painful, difficult art stemming from their experiences as outsiders. They rob audiences of the space and tools necessary to engage art thoughtfully and in good faith. They make our world a poorer, harsher place, clannish and merciless, and smother beauty in its cradle.
1.18. Market Anarchism
1.18.1. Markets Not Capitalism anarchism
This is a wide, varied, interesting, intellectually stimulating, and exciting collection of essays from all throughout history discussing various aspects of left-wing market anarchism, the school of anarchism I adhere to. It's really interesting how my reading of accelerationism aligns with what's said in this book, just framed in a slightly different way. In fact, one of the essays I mirrored regarding unconditional accelerationism actually cites one of the key modern LWMA luminaries, Kevin Carson!
This series of essays deals with deliniating the market from capitalism, showing how — as accelerationists might phrase it — the market's deterritorializing and decoding forces of creative destruction would inevitably tear down all the rigid, centralizing, hierarchical edifaces of capital were it not for capitalism's own reterritorializing and recentralizing forces. But while accelerationists usually remain in the abstract realm of cybernetics, systems theory, and Marxist economic analysis, as well as theory-fiction — all of which is useful in the task of creating new subjectivities prepared for postcapitalism — Markets Not Capitalism rolls its sleeves up, shoves its arms up to the elbows in the machinery of Capital, and shows us how it works, through Tucker's three monopolies among other things.
The essays don't stop there, though — they outline various aspects of how a pure freed market, these deterritorializing forces unleashed, might achieve the specific ends socialists set out to achieve, how they might open up new avenues, through the tearing down of hierarchies of power and extractivism, for what we now call the poor to thrive, for the environment to be protected, and for us to provide ourselves and each other good healthcare — all the concerns that might be brought up in opposition to markets.
It also contains a rousing defense of these deterritorial forces, one which made me, at least, only want to lean into them (this was the first work of anarchist theory I read, although I did read only some of the essays; most of those are are mirrored directly here as well, but I still made the effort to convert MNC to HTML because I plan to go back for more).
Table of contents:
MARKETS NOT CAPITALISM ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS Introduction THE MARKET FORM THE MARKET ANARCHIST TRADITION THE NATURAL HABITAT OF THE MARKET ANARCHIST PART ONE: The Problem of Deformed Markets THE FREED MARKET STATE SOCIALISM AND ANARCHISM How Far They Agree, and Wherein They Differ
- General Idea of the Revolution in the Nineteenth
MARKETS FREED FROM CAPITALISM PART TWO Identities and Isms
- Market Anarchism as Stigmergic Socialism
- Armies that Overlap
THE INDIVIDUALIST AND THE COMMUNIST A Dialogue
- A Glance at Communism
- Advocates of Freed Markets Should Oppose Capitalism
- Anarchism without Hyphens
- What Laissez Faire?
- Libertarianism through Thick and Thin
SOCIALISM: WHAT IT IS
- Socialist Ends, Market Means
PART THREE Ownership
- A Plea for Public Property
- From Whence Do Property Titles Arise?
- The Gift Economy of Property
FAIRNESS AND POSSESSION
- The Libertarian Case against Intellectual Property Rights
PART FOUR Corporate Power and Labor Solidarity Contributors
- Corporations versus the Market, or Whip Conflation Now
- Does Competition Mean War?
- Economic Calculation in the Corporate Commonwealth
- Big Business and the Rise of American Statism
- Regulation: The Cause, Not the Cure, of the Financial Crisis
- Industrial Economics
- Labor Struggle in a Free Market
- Should Labor Be Paid or Not?
PART FIVE Neoliberalism, Privatization, and Redistribution Contributors
- Free Market Reforms and the Reduction of Statism
FREE TRADE IS FAIR TRADE
- Two Words on "Privatization"
- Where Are the Specifics?
- Confiscation and the Homestead Principle
PART SIX Inequality and Social Safety Nets LET THE FREE MARKET EAT THE RICH! Economic Entropy as Revolutionary Redistribution
- Individualism and Inequality
- How Government Solved the Health Care Crisis
- The Poverty of the Welfare State
PART SEVEN Barriers to Entry and Fixed Costs of Living
- How "Intellectual Property" Impedes Competition
- The American Land Question
ENGLISH ENCLOSURES AND SOVIET COLLECTIVIZATION Two Instances of an Anti-Peasant Mode of Development
- Health Care and Radical Monopoly
PART EIGHT Freed-Market Regulation: Social Activism and Spontaneous Order REGULATION RED HERRING Why There's No Such Thing as an Unregulated Market
- We Are Market Forces
- Platonic Productivity
- Libertarianism and Anti-Racism
- Aggression and the Environment
- The Clean Water Act versus Clean Water
- Context-Keeping and Community Organizing
1.18.2. TODO Anarchists Against Democracy In Their Own Words anarchism philosophy
Some modern anarchists seem to worship democracy. Most liberals do. This is a collection of criticisms of it from most major anarchists.
1.18.3. Anarchy without Hyphens (1980) anarchism philosophy
An eloquent, concise statement of the idea that anarchism means a rejection of any imposed authority, and nothing more. It is "the hammer that smashes the chains" but it does not dictate what we should do after, in the space created by that smashing, except that it should not impose authority. Everything else is up to us. And any ideology that dictates one specific way of organizing "after anarchy has come" (whatever that means) is simply not really anarchism, but something else, like communism.
1.18.4. Anarchy in the U.K. anarchism history
A great short little article walking through all the ways people have protected themselves in each other without the state historically in England. While none of these ways are close to perfect, they show that there are alternatives to the state that have worked in the past.
1.18.5. Anatomy of the State anarchism philosophy
Despite my many disagreements with Rothbard, my revulsion with his paleoconservative turn, and my even greater disagreements with his intellectual heirs such as Hoppe, some of his writings are quite good. This is one of them. There are, of course, areas where I'd refocus his analysis, listed below, but in general it's very good, and I recommend reading it, just taken with a good-size grain of salt.
Some areas where I'd change what he said if I was writing it include (but aren't limited to):
- his belief that the greatest evil and aggression of the state is the invasion of private property is laughable,
- his confusion of capitalism with simply free(d) market cooperation such that he thinks states are "anti-capitalist" is fucking hilarious,
- he cites John C. Calhoun pointing out that a constitution and bill of rights means nothing if those governed by a state so "bound" cannot directly enforce those rights against that state somehow, or nullify violating state laws, and if the state is "a judge in its own case" regarding whether it's adhering to them, and then points out quite astutely that Calhoun's solution to this only protects individuals from federal, but not state, encroachment. He doesn't bother to realize why that is the case – that it's very convenient for a racist slaver "philosopher" to suggest a system where the federal government's laws can be blocked, but the states can do whatever they like
1.18.6. Confiscation and the Homestead Principle (1969) anarchism philosophy economics
One of the few essays by Rothbard that, even after my move away from anarcho-capitalism, I still really like, probably because its from the time when he was courting the New Left, instead of trying to create a paleoconservative form of "libertarianism," and so its ideals and projects are more compatible with mutualist ideas. In this case, he advocates for the giving of public propery, and any property gained through state violence, expropriation, or funding, to the people that actually occupy, use, and maintain it!
1.18.7. Corporations versus the Market; or, Whip Conflation Now anarchism economics
In this essay Roderick Long argues, successfully in my opinion, that corporate power is actually antithetical to an actually freed market, both because corporations naturally fear constant competition and shifting market demands, which will naturally break their power, and so will need to use state power to protect their position, and because corporate power is actually, historically, bought and protected (from competition, but also externalities, diseconomies of scale, etc) by means of substantial explicit, incidental, and implicit subsidies for big business on the part of the government. Thus, he argues, we should stop conflating advocacy for a free(d) market with advocacy for corporate capitalism.
1.18.8. Economic Calculation in the Corporate Commonwealth, Hierarchy or the Market, and Contract Feudalism philosophy anarchism
These essays show clearly and concretely why, if the Austrians were consistent in their critiques of the information, incentive, calculation, and ethical problems of centralization, authoritarianism, and surveillance, they would also have to be anticapitalist. These critiques are excellent and unique in providing excellent efficiency arguments against capitalism that don't rely on ideas about "rational planning."
1.18.9. From Whence Do Property Titles Arise? anarchism philosophy
An account of how mutualist property titles might arise from anarchist conditions and concerns, as a defense of market anarchism from communist anarchists.
1.18.10. In Defense of Public Space anarchism philosophy economics
A defense of public commons against more propertiarian arguments (based on the tragedy of the commoons) against it, and a gesture at why public commons are a very necessary corrective against the ways in which everything being private space could curtail autonomy. Useful as a critique of Hoppeans.
1.18.11. Instead of a Book, by a Man Too Busy to Write One: A Fragmentary Exposition of Philosophical Anarchism anarchism
Benjamin Tucker was one of the very first and most influential individualist anarchists, and many of his essays – which this book collects – are excellent and well worth reading, as well as being immensely influential on me. Obviously he has his rough spots (I haven't read most of Instead of a Book yet), and I'm sure personally he probably had many reprehensible beliefs as a man of his time, but the man is not what's important to me.
My favorite essays in here are:
- State Socialism and Anarchism
- Socialism: What It Is
- The Relation of the State to the Individual
- Armies That Overlap
1.18.12. Labour Struggle in a Free Market anarchism economics
An explanation of how, in a free(d) market world, workers are powerful and have many options for collectively fighting back against exploitation, but these days they have been castrated by government regulation much more than they have been superficially "helped." Useful for those worried about worker's rights in a market anarchist society.
1.18.13. Nice Shit for Everybody anarchism philosophy
So many anarchists seem to want an end-state world much like Anarres from The Dispossessed – living gray, ascetic lives with the bare minimum of necessities meted out to us by centrally planned and centrally controlled storehouses. They seem to want to reach equality by making nearly everyone worse off, instead of trying to lift everyone up as high as possible – and yes, that will probably require the relinquishing of many luxuries on the part of first world inhabitants, especially middle class suburbanites and above, but the goal isn't that relinquishment, the goal is the enrichment of as many as possible as much as possible. This very short essay is a statement of rejection of that ideology.
1.18.14. TODO Property is Theft! A Pierre-Joseph Proudhon Anthology philosophy anarchism economics
Proudhon is a massively underrated, deeply interesting thinker elucidating a form of anarchy that has been lost, but that I think is worth exploring, since it comes from outside the pure social anarchy and Marxist anarchy traditions found today. This reader compiles the most important parts of his otherwise often long and difficult works, including some brand new translations. I haven't read much of his yet, but I really intend to go through this.
1.18.15. Revealed Preference: A Parable anarchism economics
An excellent and enlightening exposition of why markets and market pricing are extremely helpful in resolving resource allocation problems – even when you care about equity! – in comparison even to just face to face communication.
1.18.16. Scratching By: How Government Creates Poverty as We Know It anarchism economics
An exposition of how the government takes away options that poor people would have otherwise had for supporting themselves and caring for each other, or criminalizes them, making poverty much more terrifying and dangerous and difficult than it would otherwise have to be. None of these options the government takes away are ideal, of course – some are dirty, or fire-prone, and so on, which is the guise under which the government steals them away – but they are better than jail, constant repossession of your belongings and destruction of your shelter, starvation, beatings, or death, and often better than helpless reliance on a centralized bureaucratic state organization that doesn't have to care about you and uses the money of other people who themselves don't personally care about you (and is thus incentivized to skimp on helping you).
1.18.17. TODO Seeing Like A State: How Certain Schemes to Improve the Human Condition Have Failed anarchism economics philosophy
This is another one I haven't read, but the ideas about the impossibility of top down planning and modernist totalizing systems from which have percolated already deeply into my head from other things I've read. I look forward to reading it.
1.18.18. The Gift Economy of Property anarchism philosophy
An interesting intellectual play, coming from property rights from another angle.
1.18.19. THe Modern Business Corporation versus the Free Market? anachism economics
Although I'm not a fan of natural law arguments, this is an interesting article making the case that the corporate form is ultimately a child of the state, and I think the argument might possibly offer components that can be applied outside a natural law framework, by just thinking about how we might constitute economic and social norms that make the corporate form impossible in the ways he proposes natural laws do.
1.18.20. The Network: A Parody of the Discourse anarchism economics parody
This is a short parody of anti-market anarchists which operates by replacing "market" (a network of trade) with just the abstract concept of networks of individual actors, to show how absurd their arguments truly are.
1.18.21. The Question of Copyright philosophy anarchism
This is a great takedown of the idea of copyright from an anarchist egoist perspective. Written in a slightly oldtimey manner and not dealing with any "new developments," but it's funny as hell and the arguments are still sound all these years later.
1.18.22. The Right to Self-Treatment anarchism economics
A vision for how medical care could be made radically more decentralized and accessible, without falling into the trap of single payer healthcare:
Finally: I object strenuously to those who see a single-payer system, or a government-controlled delivery system like the UK’s National Health, as the solution. I’d like to give those who talk about healthcare being a “right” the benefit of the doubt, and assume they just don’t understand the implications of what they’re saying. But when you talk about education, healthcare, or anything else being a “right,” what that means in practice is that you get it in the (rationed) amount and form the State wants you to have, and buying it in the form you want becomes much more difficult (if not criminalized). It means the providers of the service will be cartelized, and that the provision of the service will be regulated according to the professional culture and institutional mindset of the cartels. As with “public” education, “public” healthcare means that the existing “professional” institutional culture is locked into place, but that you get their services at taxpayer expense.
Making something a “right” that requires labor to produce also carries another implication: slavery. You can’t have a “right” to any good or service unless somebody else has a corresponding obligation to provide it. And if you’re obligated to provide a good or service at a cost determined by somebody else, you’re a slave. Nobody is born with a “right” to somebody else’s labor-product: as Lilburne said, nobody is born with a saddle on his back, and nobody is born booted and spurred to ride him.
1.18.23. The Use of Knowledge in Society anarchism economics
Although Hayek's knowledge problem argument is often put to use by conservatives and libertarians, that doesn't mean it isn't correct – and in more consistent hands, it militates strongly against any form of hierarchy or centralization at all, not just the much-feared socialist bureaucracy.
1.18.24. Why Market Exchange Doesn’t Have to Lead to Capitalism anarchism economics
This is a good brief, high level explanation by Kevin Carson as to why a freed market, absent the various monopolies that the state enforces on behalf of capitalists, would not necessarily result in the same distortions, inequalities, and exploitations we find under capitalism. To those, I'd add a few of my own:
- There is no such thing as a free market simpliciter; the nature of the market is always defined by particular property (and other) norms, and mutualist property norms of occupacy and use for personal possessions, and usufruct for things like land, substantially change the possibilities and incentives of a market. For instance:
- It would be impossible to have large economic organizations with direct control over or ownership of branches in different locations, because, if occupancy and use constitute ownership, the local people working at a branch would automatically be considered to be the ones that actually own any capital there, and since intellectual property can't be occupied, it couldn't be used to still keep such local branches in line. This means you wouldn't get big corporations (or even co-ops) steamrolling local businesses, because if they tried that, whatever local branch they created would be automatically converted into a local business! The only way to have large organizations like that with multiple locations would be to have fundamentally independent entities coordinate via federation.
- While global trade would still be possible (and necessary), it would be impossible for any kind of economic organization to fire all its local workers and ship all of its jobs overseas while keeping its management structure well paid and in tact, not only because there would be no third world to exploit, but also because the workers would be the management structure, and they would be unlikely to push for the obliteration of their own livelihoods.
- Extraction of natural resources bypassing local communities would be impossible.
- In a capitalist society, you can turn simply owning some piece of wealth into a way to generate more wealth for you without you having to do any more work through rent-seeking behavior like paying wage laborers to work it, renting it out, loaning it, etc. This means that all wealth that you own can generate more wealth for you at some conversion ratio, and then that wealth can generate more wealth, and so you can reach geometric wealth growth. Whereas, in a mutualist economy where you can only own what you personally occupy and use, then that strategy is not open to you. The only way that gaining more wealth can make more wealth for you is if it makes your, personal, labor-hours more productive – and there are significant diminishing returns there, as well as significant limits, since there are only so many things you can regularly use or occupy, and only so many hours a day you can work. Thus, what was once geometric is converted to logorithmic. There will be inequalities, yes, but since they won't come as a result of exploitation, there's no reason to worry about that, and they'll never be able to become so great as to threaten to create a significant power structure or centralization of wealth.
1.18.25. Health Care and Radical Monopoly anarchism market
In a recent article for Tikkun, Dr. Arnold Relman argued that the versions of health care reform currently proposed by “progressives” all primarily involve financing health care and expanding coverage to the uninsured rather than addressing the way current models of service delivery make it so expensive. Editing out all the pro forma tut-tutting of “private markets,” the substance that’s left is considerable:
"What are those inflationary forces? . . . [M]ost important among them are the incentives in the payment and organization of medical care that cause physicians, hospitals and other medical care facilities to focus at least as much on income and profit as on meeting the needs of patients. . . . The incentives in such a system reward and stimulate the delivery of more services. That is why medical expenditures in the U.S. are so much higher than in any other country, and are rising more rapidly. . . . Physicians, who supply the services, control most of the decisions to use medical resources. . . .
Physicians and ambulatory care and diagnostic facilities are largely paid on a piecework basis for each item of service provided."
As a health care worker, I have personally witnessed… mutual log-rolling between specialists and the never-ending addition of tests to the bill without any explanation to the patient. The patient simply lies in bed and watches an endless parade of unknown doctors poking their heads in the door for a microsecond, along with an endless series of lab techs drawing body fluids for one test after another that’s “been ordered,” with no further explanation. The post-discharge avalanche of bills includes duns from two or three dozen doctors, most of whom the patient couldn’t pick out of a police lineup.
…
More generally, the system is racked by artificial scarcity, as editor Sheldon Richman observed in an interview a few months back. For example, licensing systems limit the number of practitioners and arbitrarily impose levels of educational overhead beyond the requirements of the procedures actually being performed.
Libertarians sometimes—and rightly—use “grocery insurance” as an analogy to explain medical price inflation: If there were such a thing as grocery insurance, with low deductibles, to provide third-party payments at the checkout register, people would be buying a lot more rib-eye and porterhouse steaks and a lot less hamburger.
The problem is we’ve got a regulatory system that outlaws hamburger and compels you to buy porterhouse if you’re going to buy anything at all. It’s a multiple-tier finance system with one tier of service… No matter how simple and straightforward the procedure, you can’t hire someone who’s adequately trained just to perform the service you need; you’ve got to pay amortization on a full med school education and residency.
Drug patents have the same effect, increasing the cost per pill by up to 2,000 percent… Drug-company propaganda about high R&D costs, as a justification for patents to recoup capital outlays, is highly misleading. A major part of the basic research for identifying therapeutic pathways is done in small biotech startups, or at taxpayer expense in university laboratories, and then bought up by big drug companies. The main expense of the drug companies is the FDA-imposed testing regimen—and most of that is not to test the version actually marketed, but to secure patent lockdown on other possible variants of the marketed version. In other words, gaming the patent system grossly inflates R&D spending.
The prescription medicine system, along with state licensing of pharmacists and Drug Enforcement Administration licensing of pharmacies, is another severe restraint on competition. At the local natural-foods cooperative I can buy foods in bulk, at a generic commodity price; even organic flour, sugar, and other items are usually cheaper than the name-brand conventional equivalent at the supermarket. Such food cooperatives have their origins in the food-buying clubs of the 1970s, which applied the principle of bulk purchasing. The pharmaceutical licensing system obviously prohibits such bulk purchasing (unless you can get a licensed pharmacist to cooperate).
The main impetus to creating the licensing systems on which artificial scarcity depends came from the medical profession early in the twentieth century. As described by Richman:
"Accreditation of medical schools regulated how many doctors would graduate each year. Licensing similarly metered the number of practitioners and prohibited competitors, such as nurses and paramedics, from performing services they were perfectly capable of performing. Finally, prescription laws guaranteed that people would have to see a doctor to obtain medicines they had previously been able to get on their own."
The medical licensing cartels were also the primary force behind the move to shut down lodge practice, mentioned above.
Health care is a classic example of what Ivan Illich, in Tools for Conviviality, called a “radical monopoly.” State-sponsored crowding out makes other, cheaper (but often more appropriate) forms of treatment less usable, and renders cheaper (but adequate) treatments artificially scarce. Artificially centralized, high-tech, and skill-intensive ways of doing things make it harder for ordinary people to translate their skills and knowledge into use-value.